R. M. Hare Reply to Flew
From "Symposium on Theology and Falsification,"
Antony Flew, R. M. Hare and Basil Mitchell.
I wish to make it clear that I shall not try to defend
Christianity in particular, but religion in general - not because I
do not believe in Christianity, but because you cannot understand
what Christianity is, until you have understood what religion is.
I must begin by confessing that, on the ground marked out by
Flew, he seems to me to be completely victorious. I therefore shift
my ground by relating another parable.
A certain lunatic is convinced that all dons want to murder
him. His friends introduce him to all the mildest and most
respectable dons that they can find, and after each of them has
retired, they say, 'You see, he doesn't really want to murder you;
he spoke to you in a most cordial manner; surely you are convinced
now?' But the lunatic replies, 'Yes, but that was only his
diabolical cunning; he's really plotting against me the whole
time, like the rest of them; I know it I tell you'. However many
kindly dons are produced, the reaction is still the same.
Now we say that such a person is deluded. But what is he deluded
about? About the truth or falsity of an assertion? Let us apply
Flew's test to him. There is no behavior of dons that can be enacted
which he will accept as counting against his theory; and therefore
his theory, on this test, asserts nothing. But it does not follow
that there is no difference between what he thinks about dons and
what most of us think about them-otherwise we should not call him a
lunatic and ourselves sane, and dons would have no reason to feel
uneasy about his presence in Oxford.
Let us call that, in which we differ from this lunatic, our
respective bliks . He has an insane blik about dons; we have a sane
one. It is important to realize that we have a sane one, not no blik
at all; for there must be two sides to any argument - if he has a
wrong blik , then those who are right about dons must have a right
one. Flew has shown that a blik does not consist in an assertion or
system of them; but nevertheless it is very important to have the
right blik .
Let us try to imagine what it would be like to have different
bliks about other things than dons. When I am driving my car, it
sometimes occurs to me to wonder whether my movements of the
steering-wheel will always continue to be followed by corresponding
alterations in the direction of the car. I have never had a steering
failure, though I have had skids, which must be similar. Moreover, I
know enough about how the steering of my car is made, to know the
sort of thing that would have to go wrong for the steering to fail -
steel joints would have to part, or steel rods break, or something -
but how do I know that this won't happen? The truth is, I don't
know; I just have a blik about steel and its properties, so that
normally I trust the steering of my car; but I find it not at all
difficult to imagine what it would be like to lose this blik and
acquire the opposite one. People would say I was silly about steel;
but there would be no mistaking the reality of the difference
between our respective bliks - for example, I should never go in a
motor-car . Yet I should hesitate to say that the difference between
us was the difference between contradictory assertions. No amount of
safe arrivals or bench-tests will remove my blik and restore the
normal one; for my blik is compatible with any finite number of such
tests.
It was Hume who
taught us that our whole commerce with the world depends upon our
bliks about the world; and that differences between bliks about the
world cannot be settled by observation of what happens in the world.
That was why, having performed the interesting experiment of
doubting the ordinary man's blik about the world, and showing that
no proof could be given to make us adopt one blik rather than
another, he turned to backgammon to take his mind off the problem.
It seems, indeed, to be impossible even to formulate as an assertion
the normal blik about the world which makes me put my confidence in
the future reliability of steel joints, in the continued ability of
the road to support my car, and not gape beneath it revealing
nothing below; in the general non- homicidal tendencies of dons; in
my own continued wellbeing (in some sense of that word that I may
not now fully understand) if I continue to do what is right
according to my lights; in the general likelihood of people like
Hitler coming to a bad end. But perhaps a formulation less
inadequate than most is to be found in the Psalms: 'The earth is
weak and all the inhabiters thereof: I bear up the pillars of it".
The mistake of the position which Flew selects for attack is to
regard this kind of talk as some sort of explanation, as scientists
are accustomed to use the word. As such, it would obviously be
ludicrous. We no longer believe in God as an Atlas - "nous
n'avons pas besoin de cette hypothese."("we
are no longer in need of such an hypothesis.") .But it is
nevertheless true to say that, as Hume saw, without a blik there can
be no explanation; for it is by our blik that we decide what is and
what is not an explanation. Suppose we believed that everything that
happened, happened by pure chance. This would not of course be an
assertion; for it is compatible with anything happening or not
happening, and so, incidentally, is its contradictory. But if we had
this belief, we should not be able to explain or predict or plan
anything. Thus, although we should not be asserting anything
different from those of a more normal belief, there would be a great
difference between us; and this is the sort of difference that there
is between those who really believe in God and those who really
disbelieve in him.
The word 'really' is important, and may excite suspicion. I put
it in, because when people have had a good Christian upbringing, as
have most of those who now profess not to believe in any sort of
religion, it is very hard to discover what they really believe. The
reason why they find it so easy to think that they are not
religious, is that they have never got into the frame of mind of one
who suffers from the doubts to which religion is the answer. Not for
them the terrors of the primitive jungle. Having abandoned some of
the more picturesque fringes of religion, they think that they have
abandoned the whole thing - whereas in fact they still have got, and
could not live without, a religion of a comfortably substantial,
albeit highly sophisticated, kind, which differs from that of many
'religious people' in little more than this, that 'religious people'
like to sing Psalms about theirs - a very natural and proper thing
to do. But nevertheless there may be a big difference lying behind -
the difference between two people who, though side by side, are
walking in different directions. I do not know in what direction
Flew is walking; perhaps he does not know either. But we have had
some examples recently of various ways in which one can walk away
from Christianity, and there are any number of possibilities. After
all, man has not changed biologically since primitive times; it is
his religion that has changed, and it can easily change again. And
if you do not think that such changes make a difference, get
acquainted with some Sikhs and some Mussulmans of the same Punjabi
stock; you will find them quite different sorts of people.
There is an important difference between Flew's parable and my
own which we have not yet noticed. The explorers do not mind about
their garden; they discuss it with interest, but not with concern.
But my lunatic, poor fellow, minds about dons; and I mind about the
steering of my car; it often has people in it that I care for. It is
because I mind very much about what goes on in the garden in which I
find myself, that I am unable to share the explorers' detachment.